Excerpt from On
Political Equality by Robert A. Dahl
Is Political Equality a Reasonable Goal?
If we make two assumptions, each of which hard to reject in reasonable
and open public discourse, the case for political equality and democracy
becomes extraordinarily powerful. The first is the moral judgment that all
human beings are of equal intrinsic worth, that no person is intrinsically superior
to another, and that the good or interests of each person must be given equal
consideration. Let me call this the assumption of intrinsic equality.
Even if we accept this moral judgment, the deeply troublesome question
immediately arises: who or what group is best qualified to decide what the good
or interests of a person really are? Clearly the answer will vary depending on
the situation, the kinds of decisions, and the persons involved.
But if we restrict our focus to the government of a state, then it seems to me that the safest and most prudent assumption would run something like this: Among adults no persons are so definitely better qualified than others to govern that they should be entrusted with complete and final authority over the government of the state.
Although we might reasonably add refinements and qualifications to this
prudential judgment, for at least three reasons it is difficult to see how any
substantially different proposition could be supported. First, Acton's famous
and oft quoted proposition appears to express a fundamental truth about human
beings: power corrupts, and absolute power corrupts absolutely. Whatever the
intentions of rulers may be at the outset of their rule, any commitment they
may have to serving "the public good" is likely to be transformed in
time into an identification of "the public good" with the maintenance
of the their own powers and privileges. Second, just as free discussion and
controversy are, as John Stuart Mill famously argued, essential to the pursuit
of truth—or, if you prefer,
to reasonably justifiable judgments—a government unchecked by citizens who are free to
discuss and oppose the policies of their leaders is more likely to blunder,
sometimes disastrously, as modern authoritarian regimes have amply demonstrated.
Finally, consider the most crucial historical cases in which substantial
numbers of persons were denied equal citizenship: does anyone really believe
today that when the working classes, women, and racial and ethnic minorities were
excluded from political participation, their interests were adequately
considered and protected by those who were privileged to govern them?
I do not mean to say that the reasons I have given were in the minds of
the persons who brought about greater political equality. I am simply saying
that moral and prudential judgments offer strong support for political equality
as a desirable and reasonable goal or ideal.
POLITICAL EQUALITY
AND DEMOCRACY
If we conclude that political equality is desirable in governing a state
(though not necessarily in all other human associations), how may it be
achieved? It almost goes without saying that the only political system for
governing a state that derives its legitimacy and its political institutions
from the idea of political equality is a democracy. What political institutions
are necessary in order for a political system to qualify as a democracy? And
why these institutions?
IDEAL VS. ACTUAL
We can't answer these questions satisfactorily, I believe, without a
concept of an ideal democracy. For the same reasons that Aristotle found it
useful to describe his three ideal constitutions in order to classify actual
systems, a description of an ideal democracy provides a model against which to compare
various actual systems. Unless we have a conception of the ideal against which
to compare the actual, our reasoning will be circular or purely arbitrary:
e.g., "the United States, Britain, France, and Norway are all democracies;
therefore, the political institutions they all have in common must be the basic
institutions that are necessary to democracy; therefore, since these countries
possess these institutions, they must be democracies."
We need to keep in mind that a description of an "ideal" system
can serve two different but entirely compatible purposes. One is to assist in
empirical or scientific theory. The other is to help us make moral judgments by
providing an ideal end or goal. These are often confused, though an "ideal"
in the first sense does not necessarily imply an "ideal" in the
other.
In empirical theory the function of an ideal system is to describe the
characteristics or operation of that system under a set of perfect (ideal)
conditions. Galileo inferred the rate at which an object would fall in a vacuum—i.e., under ideal
conditions—by measuring the
speed of a marble rolling down an inclined plane. Obviously he did not and
could not measure its rate of fall in a vacuum. Yet his law of falling bodies
remains valid today. It is not uncommon in physics to formulate hypotheses
concerning the behavior of an object or force under ideal conditions that
cannot be perfectly attained in actual experiments but that can be
satisfactorily approximated. In a similar spirit, when the German sociologist Max
Weber described "three pure types of legitimate authority" he
commented that "the usefulness of the above classification can only be
judged by its results in promoting systematic analysis . . . [N]one of these
three ideal types . . . is usually to be found in historical cases in ‘pure’ form."
An ideal in the second sense is understood as a desirable goal, one
probably not perfectly achievable in practice, but a standard to which we ought
to aspire, and against which we can measure the good or value of what has been
achieved, what actually exists.
A definition and description of democracy may be intended to serve only
the first purpose; or it may serve the second as well. As an aid to empirical
theory, a conception of democracy may come not from an advocate but from a
critic for whom even the ideal is unsatisfactory, or simply irrelevant to human
experience because of the enormous gap between the goal and any possibility of
a satisfactory approximation.
IDEAL DEMOCRACY
Although an ideal democracy might be portrayed in many ways, a useful
starting point is the etymological origins of the term: demos + kratia,
rule by "the people." In order to leave open the question of just
which "people" are provided with full political equality, instead of "the
people" let me briefly use the more neutral term "demos."
At a minimum an ideal democracy would, I believe, require these
features:
·
Effective participation. Before a policy is adopted
by the association, all the members of the demos must have equal and effective
opportunities for making known to other members their views about what the
policy should be.
·
the decision will finally be made, every member
must have an equal and effective opportunity to vote, and all votes must be
counted as equal.
·
Gaining enlightened understanding. Within a
reasonable amount of time, each member would have equal and effective
opportunities for learning about the relevant alternative policies and their
likely consequences.
·
Final control of the agenda. The demos would have
the exclusive opportunity to decide how (and if ) its members chose which
matters are to be placed on the agenda. Thus the democratic process required by
the three preceding features would never be closed. The policies of the
association would always be open to change by the demos, if its members chose
to do so.
·
Inclusion. Every member of the demos would be
entitled to participate in the ways just described: effective participation,
equality in voting, seeking an enlightened understanding of the issues, and
exercising final control over the agenda.
·
Fundamental rights. Each of the necessary features
of an ideal democracy prescribes a right that is itself a necessary part of an
ideal democratic order: a right to participate, a right to have one’s vote counted
equally with the votes of others, a right to search for the knowledge necessary
in order to understand the issue on the agenda, and a right to participate on
an equal footing with one's fellow citizens in exercising final control over
the agenda. Democracy consists, then, not only of political processes. It is
also necessarily a system of fundamental rights.
ACTUAL DEMOCRATIC
SYSTEMS
Political philosophers from Aristotle to Rousseau and later have
generally insisted that no actual political system is likely to meet fully the
requirements of the ideal. Although the political institutions of actual
democracies may be necessary in order for a political system to attain a
relatively high level of democracy, they may not be, indeed almost certainly
will not be, sufficient to achieve anything like perfect or ideal democracy.
Yet the institutions amount to a large step toward the ideal, as presumably
they did in Athens when citizens, leaders, and political philosophers named
their system a democracy—i.e., an actual if not ideal democracy—or in the United
States when Tocqueville, like most others in America and elsewhere,
unhesitatingly called it a democracy.
If a unit is small in numbers and area, the political institutions of
assembly democracy could readily be seen as fulfilling the requirements for a "government
by the people." The citizens would be free to learn as much as they could
about the proposals that are to come before them. They could discuss policies
and proposals with their fellow citizens, seek out information from members
they regard as better informed, and consult written or other sources. They
could meet at a convenient place—Pnyx Hill in Athens, the Forum in Rome, the Palazzo
Ducale in Venice, the town hall in a New England village. There, under the
guidance of a neutral moderator, within reasonable time limits they could
discuss, debate, amend, propose. Finally, they could cast their votes, all
votes being counted equal, with the votes of a majority prevailing.
It is easy to see, then, why assembly democracy is sometimes thought to
be much closer to the ideal than a representative system could possibly be, and
why the most ardent advocates of assembly democracy sometimes insist, like Rousseau
in the Social Contract, that the term representative democracy is
self-contradictory. Yet views like these have failed to win many converts.
THE POLITICAL
INSTITUTIONS OF REPRESENTATIVE DEMOCRACY
Throughout the nineteenth and twentieth centuries in Europe and the
English-speaking countries a set of political institutions needed for
democratic representative governments evolved that, taken as a whole, was
entirely new in human history. Despite important differences in constitutional structures,
these basic political institutions are similar in their broad outlines. The
most important are:
·
Important government decisions and policies are
directly or indirectly adopted by, or accountable to, officials who are chosen
in popular elections.
·
Citizens are entitled to participate freely in fair
and reasonably frequent elections in which coercion is uncommon.
·
Citizens are entitled to run for and serve in
elective offices, though requirements as to age and place of residence may be
imposed.
·
Citizens may express themselves publicly over a
broad range of politically relevant subjects, without danger of severe
punishment.
·
All citizens are entitled to seek out independent
sources of information from other citizens, newspapers, and many other sources;
moreover, sources of information not under the control of the government or any
single group actually exist and are effectively protected by law in their expression.
·
In full contrast to the prevailing view in earlier
democracies and republics that political "factions" were a danger to
be avoided, both theory and practice came to insist that in order for citizens
to achieve their various rights they must possess a further right to form and
participate in relatively independent associations and organizations, including
independent political parties and interest groups.
Political institutions like these developed in different countries under
various political and historical circumstances, and they were not necessarily
fostered only by democratic impulses. Yet it would become increasingly apparent
that they were necessary institutions for achieving a satisfactory level of democracy
in a political unit, like a country, that was too large for assembly democracy.
The relation between the institutions of actual (large scale) democracy
and the requirements of an ideal democracy can be summarized thus:
In a unit as
large as a country, these political institutions are necessary:
|
in order to
satisfy these criteria of ideal democracy:
|
1. Elected
representatives
|
Effective
participation
Control of the
agenda
|
2. Free, fair,
and frequent elections
|
Voting equality
Effective
participation
|
3. Freedom of
expression
|
Effective
participation
Enlightened
understanding
Control of the
agenda
|
4. Alternative
sources of information
|
Effective
participation
Enlightened
understanding
Control of the
agenda
|
5. Associational
autonomy Effective participation
|
Enlightened
understanding
Control of the
agenda
|
6. Inclusion of
all members of the demos
|
Effective
participation
Voting equality
Enlightened
understanding
Control of the
agenda
|
LEGITIMATE LIMITS
ON THE POWER OF THE DEMOS
If citizens disagree on policies, whose views should prevail? The
standard answer in democratic systems is that the decision must follow the will
of the majority of citizens, or in representative systems, the majority of
their representatives in the legislative
body. Because the principle of majority rule and its justification have been
the subject of careful and, I believe, convincing analyses from John Locke to
the present day, I shall not undertake to justify majority rule except to say
that no other rule appears to be consistent with the assumption that all
citizens are entitled to be treated as political equals. Although majority rule
is not without problems, these are not at issue here.
To return now to our question: If we assume that membership in the demos
and the necessary political institutions have been satisfactorily established,
what limits may properly be placed on the authority of the demos to
enact laws, and more concretely, on the authority of a majority of the
members of the demos?
NECESSARY
DEMOCRACTIC RIGHTS
If we believe in the desirability and feasibility of representative democracy
for large-scale political systems, and if the institutions I have just
mentioned, together with their requisite rights, are necessary for
representative democracy, then it follows that actions that would significantly
weaken or even destroy these rights cannot be legitimate and may properly be
placed outside the legal and constitutional authority of majorities. Although a
thorough examination of the issue would take us further than I wish to go here,
as a matter of straightforward logic it seems obvious that the fundamental rights
necessary to democracy itself cannot legitimately be infringed by
majorities whose actions are justified only by the principle of political
equality. Simply put, if we assume that:
1. Achieving political equality is a desirable and feasible goal.
2. Majority rule is justified only as a means of achieving political
equality.
3. A democratic political system is a necessary (though not sufficient)
condition for achieving political equality.
4. And certain rights are necessary (though not sufficient) for fully
achieving a democratic political system.
Then it follows that:
·
To deny or infringe on these necessary rights would
harm a democratic political system.
·
By harming a democratic system, these denials or
infringements on necessary rights would harm political equality.
·
If majority rule is justified only as a means of
achieving political equality (assumption 2, above), the principle of majority
rule cannot reasonably justify actions that inflict harm on rights necessary to
a democratic system.
It would not be inconsistent with democratic beliefs, then, to impose
limits on the authority of a majority to undertake actions that would destroy
an institution like freedom of speech that is necessary if a democratic system
is to exist. This is the intent, for example, of a Bill of Rights embedded in a
constitution that cannot be altered by ordinary majorities of 50 percent plus
one, but instead requires that amendments must be passed by supermajorities.
Logically, of course, even the members of the requisite supermajority
required for constitutional change could not logically believe both in the desirability
democracy and at the same time support a constitutional amendment that would
severely impair or destroy one of its requisites, such as freedom of speech,
free and fair elections, and others listed above.
Here we pass over the threshold from ought to is. In the world
of empirical reality, if a preponderant majority of active citizens in a
democratic country persistently believe that a right necessary to democracy is undesirable and should be sharply
limited or abolished, then that right is very likely to be curtailed. Even an
independent judiciary would be unable to stem a strong tide running steadily
against democratic rights. When a demos ceases to believe that the rights
necessary to democracy are desirable, their democracy will soon become an oligarchy
or a tyranny.
There is, however, another and more insidious route from democracy to
oligarchy. Even if most members of the demos continue to believe in the
desirability of these fundamental rights, they may fail to undertake the political
actions that would be necessary in order to protect and preserve those rights
from infringements imposed by political leaders who possess greater resources
for gaining their own political ends.
IS POLITICAL
EQUALITY A FEASIBLE GOAL?
These observations pose a fundamental and troubling question. Even if we
believe that political equality is a highly desirable goal, and that this goal
is best achieved in a democratic political system, is the goal really
achievable, even in a democratic system? Or do some fundamental aspects of
human beings and human society present barriers to political equality so high
that for all practical purposes the goal is and will remain so distant that we
should abandon efforts to achieve it?
The United States provides telling examples of the huge gap between the
rhetoric and reality of political equality. In the second paragraph of a
document that is otherwise a rather tedious listing of the "repeated
injuries and usurpations" inflicted by the king of Great Britain, we
encounter the famous assertion of a supposedly self-evident truth, that all men
are created equal. The authors of the American Declaration of Independence and
the fifty-five delegates to the Second Continental Congress who voted to adopt
it in July 1776, were, of course, all men, none of whom had the slightest
intention of extending the suffrage or many other basic political and civil
rights to women, who, in legal contemplation, were essentially the property of
their fathers or husbands.
"Of women," Rogers Smith writes in his masterful work on
American citizenship, "the Constitution said nothing directly. It did,
however, use masculine pronouns thirty times describing U.S. Representatives,
Senators, the Vice-President and the President . . . The salient fact . . . was
the Constitution left intact the state constitutions that denied women the franchise
and other legal and political privileges."
Nor did the worthy supporters of the Declaration intend to include
slaves or, for that matter, free persons of African origin, who were a
substantial fraction of the population in almost all the colonies that now
claimed the right to become independent self-governing republics. The principal
author of the Declaration, Thomas Jefferson, owned several hundred slaves, none
of whom he freed during his life; and he freed only five on his death. It was
not until more than four score and seven years later (to borrow a poetic phrase
from Lincoln's Gettysburg Address) that slavery was legally abolished in the
United States by force of arms and constitutional enactment. And it took yet
another century before the rights of African Americans to participate in
political life began to be effectively enforced in the American South. Now, two
generations later, Americans white and black still bear the deep wounds that
slavery and its aftermath inflicted on human equality, freedom, dignity, and
respect.
Our noble Declaration also silently excluded the people who for some
thousands of years had inhabited the lands that Europeans colonized and came to
occupy. We are all, I think, familiar with the story of how the settlers denied
homes, land, place, freedom, dignity, and humanity to these earlier peoples of
America, whose descendants even today continue to suffer from the effects of
their treatment throughout several centuries when their most elementary claims
to legal, economic, and political—not to say social— standing as equal
human beings were rejected, often by violence, a lengthy period followed more
recently by neglect and indifference.
All this in a country that visitors from Europe like Tocqueville portrayed,
quite correctly, I think, as displaying a passion for equality stronger than
they had ever observed elsewhere.
It would be easy to provide endless examples from other democratic
countries. Many Europeans would probably agree that over many centuries the
people of one of the most advanced democratic countries in the world, Britain,
have been concerned more passionately than in any other western European
country with maintaining social inequalities in the form of differences in
class and status, which in turn played out in many ways, notably in higher
education, the admirable British Civil Service, the professions, including law and
justice, and business. Until only a few years ago, unlike any other democratic
country in the world, Britain maintained the astonishing anachronism of an
upper house in its national parliament consisting overwhelmingly of hereditary peers.
The historical gap between the public rhetoric and reality of political
equality is by no means unique to the United States and Britain. In many "democratic"
countries, large parts of the adult male population were excluded from the suffrage
until late in the nineteenth century, or even until the twentieth century. And
only two "democratic" countries— New Zealand and
Australia—had extended the
suffrage to women in national elections before the 1920s. In France and
Belgium, women did not gain the suffrage in national elections until after the
Second World War. In Switzerland, where universal male suffrage was established
for males in 1848, women were not guaranteed the right to vote until 1971.
So much for the rhetorical commitment to political equality so often
asserted by leaders and by many citizens—male citizens—in "democratic" countries.
THE GROWTH OF
POLITICAL EQUALITY
Despite the obvious fact that equality has often been denied in practice
in many places, remarkably over the past several centuries many claims to
equality, including political equality, have come to be strongly reinforced by
institutions, practices, and behavior. Although this monumental historical movement
is in some respects worldwide, it has been most conspicuous, perhaps, in
democratic countries like Britain, France, the United States, the Scandinavian
countries, Holland, and many others.
In the opening pages of the first volume of Democracy in America Tocqueville
pointed to the inexorable increase in the equality of conditions among his
French countrymen "at intervals of fifty years, beginning with the
eleventh century." Nor was this revolution taking place only in his own
country: "Whithersoever we turn our eyes," he wrote, "we shall witness
the same continual revolution throughout the whole of Christendom."
"The gradual development of the equality of conditions," he
goes on to say, "is . . . a providential fact, and it possesses all the
characteristics of a Divine decree: it is universal, it is durable, it
constantly eludes all human interference, and all events as well as men contribute
to its progress."
We may wish to grant Tocqueville a certain measure of hyperbole in this
passage. We may also want to note that in his second volume several years later
he was more troubled by what he viewed as some of the undesirable consequences of
democracy and equality. Even so, he did not doubt that a continuing advance of
democracy and equality was inevitable. If today we look back to the changes
since his time, we, like Tocqueville in his own day, may well be amazed at the extent
to which ideas and practices that respect and promote political equality have
advanced across so much of the world—and, for that matter, aspects of a broader human equality
as well.
As to political equality, consider the incredible spread of democratic
ideas, institutions, and practices during the century just ended. In 1900,
forty-eight countries were fully or moderately independent countries. Of these,
only eight possessed all the other basic institutions of representative democracy,
and in only one of these, New Zealand, had women gained the right to vote.
Furthermore, these eight countries contained no more than 10 to 12 percent of
the world's population. At the opening of our present century, among some one
hundred ninety countries the political institutions and practices of modern
representative democracy, including universal suffrage, exist in around
eighty-five, at levels comparable to those in Britain, western Europe, and the
United States. These countries include almost six out of every ten inhabitants
of the globe today.
In Britain, as we all know, the working classes and women were
enfranchised, and more. Men and women of middle, lower middle, and working
class origins not only gained access to the House of Commons and its facilities
but to the cabinet and even the post of prime minister. And the hereditary peers
in the House of Lords have, after all, at last been sent packing—well, most of
them. In the United States, too, women were enfranchised; the Voting Rights Act
of 1965 protecting the right of African Americans to vote did in fact become
law; the law was actually enforced; and African Americans have become a
significant force in American political life. I wish I could say that the
miserable condition of so many Native Americans had greatly changed for the better,
but that sad legacy of human injustice remains with us.
Failures and all, if we simply assume that beliefs about equality are
always hopelessly anemic contestants in the struggle against the powerful
forces that generate inequalities, we could not possibly account for the
enormous gains for human equality over the past two centuries. Yet the question
remains: given all the obstacles to political equality, how can we account for
these gains?
A BRIEF SKETCH OF
MOVEMENTS TOWARD POLITICAL EQUALITY
To help us understand how change toward political equality may come
about despite the superior resources of the privileged strata, I want to
present a schematic portrayal of the process.
PRIVILEGE IS
JUSTIFIED BY DOCTRINE
The most highly privileged members of a society—the political, social, and economic
elites, if you will—typically espouse
and, when they can, even enforce doctrines that justify their superiority.
Often these doctrines are supported, and perhaps have been created, by
religious authorities who themselves are members of the upper strata—as with "the divine
right of kings" that over many centuries served in Europe to justify the
rule of monarchs. Philosophers also contribute to the defense of elite rule—famously and
enduringly in the case of Plato. But even the more moderate Aristotle was not
particularly sympathetic with idea of political equality. In some cases,
hierarchy and privilege may be legitimized by an official philosophy, as with
Confucianism, which prevailed for several thousand years in imperial China. In
recent totalitarian regimes, a dogmatic and unquestionable ideology has served
to give legitimacy to power and privilege: Marxism-Leninism in the Soviet Union,
Fascist doctrine in Italy, the dogmas of Nazism in Hitler's Germany.
SKEPTICISM ABOUT
ELITE DOMINANCE AMONG LOWER STRATA
Privileged elites often appear to believe that their legitimizing doctrines
are generally accepted among the lower strata: "Upstairs" assumes
that its entitlements are accepted as perfectly legitimate by the inferior
orders "Downstairs." Yet despite the fervent efforts of elites to
promote views intended to give legitimacy to their superior power and status and
their own unquestioning belief in the rightness of their entitlements, doubts
arise among many members of subordinate groups that the inferior positions
assigned to them by their self-proclaimed superiors are really justified.
James Scott has shown pretty convincingly that people who have been
relegated to subordinate status by history, structure, and elite belief systems
are much less likely to be taken in by the dominant ideology than members of
the upper strata are prone to assume. As one example, he writes that "among
the untouchables of India there is persuasive evidence that the Hindu doctrines
that would legitimize caste domination are negated, reinterpreted, or ignored. Scheduled
castes are much less likely than Brahmins to believe that the doctrine of karma
explains their present condition; instead they attribute their status to their
poverty and to an original, mythical act of injustice."
MORE FAVORABLE
CONDITIONS
Given the open or concealed rejection of the elite ideology by members
of the subordinate groups, a change in conditions, whether in ideas, beliefs,
structures, generations, or whatever, offers the subordinate groups new
opportunities to express their grievances. For a variety of reasons, the
British were unable to impose their political, economic, and social structures
on the colonials who emigrated to America in the seventeenth and eighteenth
centuries. Sheer distance across the Atlantic, the ready availability in the
colonies of property in land, new opportunities in commerce and finance, the resulting
growth of a large class of independent farmers, businessmen, and artisans, and
other differences between colonial America and the mother country o√ered the colonials
much greater opportunities to engage effectively in political life than they
had enjoyed in Britain.
GROWING PRESSURES
FOR CHANGE
With the emergence of these new opportunities, and driven by anger,
resentment, a sense of injustice, a prospect of greater individual or group
opportunities, group loyalty, or other motives, some members of the subordinate
groups begin to press for change by any available means. For example, following
the introduction of democracy in India, the members of the lower castes quickly
began to seize their new opportunities to improve their status.
SUPPORT WITHIN THE
DOMINANT STRATA
Some members of the dominant group choose to support the claims of the
subordinate strata. Insiders ally themselves with outsiders—an Upstairs rebel
takes on the cause of the discontented Downstairs. Insiders may do so for a
variety of reasons: moral convictions, compassion, opportunism, fear of the consequences of
disorder, dangers to property and the legitimacy of the regime, and even the
real or imagined possibility of revolution.
THE SUBORDINATE
STRATA MAKE GAINS
These factors culminate in a change by which the previously subordinate
strata make significant gains in power, influence, status, education, income,
or other advantages— and quite possibly all of these. For example, among
the colonials in America the percentage of white males who gained the right to
vote in elections to local and colonial legislatures was far higher than in the
home country. Sometimes, as was ultimately true in America, the gains are
achieved, at least in part, by means of a violent revolution in which the subordinate
strata overturn the dominance of the privileged strata. In many cases, however,
change occurs more gradually and peacefully, as with the expansion of the suffrage
by acts of parliament in Britain, Sweden, and other European countries, and by
constitutional amendment and congressional action in the United States.
Although specific accounts of the changes toward political equality that
have occurred in so many countries over the last several centuries would vary
enormously, these general factors would, I believe, have played a part in most
of them.